PHILOSOPHY OF MIND PDF

adminComment(0)

PDF | On Jan 1, , Sean Crawford and others published General Introduction to Philosophy of Mind: Critical Concepts in Philosophy. philosophers intending to use the book in courses in the philosophy of mind will be . She has published widely in metaphysics and philosophy of mind, most. In this book Jonathan Lowe offers a lucid and wide- ranging introduction to the philosophy of mind. Using a problem-centred approach designed to stimulate as .


Philosophy Of Mind Pdf

Author:VERLIE ESSELINK
Language:English, German, Dutch
Country:Macedonia
Genre:Lifestyle
Pages:273
Published (Last):25.02.2016
ISBN:425-3-26399-481-5
ePub File Size:22.82 MB
PDF File Size:14.35 MB
Distribution:Free* [*Register to download]
Downloads:35811
Uploaded by: WALTER

The knowledge of Mind is the highest and hardest, just because it is the most 'concrete' of sciences. The significance of that 'absolute' commandment, Know. The philosophy of mind is an area of philosophy delineated by a set of problems .. available here: thtonmonnixilon.tk). PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, BRAIN AND BEHAVIOUR Marc Stars, Lean de Bruin & Derek Strijbos Boom I Amsterdam Contents Introduction > Boom uitgevers.

Moreover, whatexactlydeterminesthe and consciousness be brain states? Is it, indeed, correct to identi- contents of your thought about Paris? Is this content entirely de- fy the mind with the brain? What is the role of behaviour in this termined by brain processes, or does it exist outside of your brain identification? And shouldn't we think that neuroscience super- as the actual city in France? And how can intentionality or content sedes,ratherthanexplains,talk of ourselvesin terms ofminds and exist in the natural world?

How can we explain it given that no mental states? In the course of the second half of the last century, other natural phenomena display this strange property of about- philosophyhasproducedquite a numberoftheoriesto answersuch ness? We will discuss this problem in Chapter 3. These In Chapter 4 we discuss the problematic fact that many of our theories will form the background against which more specific actions appear to be caused by mental states such as beliefs and philosophical puzzles with respect to the mind will be addressed in desires.

How can mental states cause physical actions? The easy subsequentchapters. Weknowthatour actionsarecaused analysis of consciousness. In Chapter 2,we shall discuss the deep by brain states.

But instead ofsolving the problem, this move deep- problems that arise when we want to characterize consciousness ens it. For if some brain states cause our actions, what purpose in such a way that it can be an explanandum for science. Most of does it serve to call these states mental as well? Isn't it sufficient to the chapter will be devoted to a specific type of consciousness that describe them as the bio-chemical processes that they are?

What philosophers refer to as 'phenomenal consciousness. Why are here is how to explain the subjective, experientiai character of our they not explanatorily redundant? This is the problem of mental experiences. We can explain what pain is by referring to how it is causation.

Navigation Bar

But with all that we still haven't explained ly debated topics, both in philosophy andin the behavioural and why pain hurts. Some philosophers have devised thought experi- brain sciences: There is a long, venerable philosophical ments that allegedly show that it is impossible to provide such an tradition of thinking about this topic.

In fact this is one of the explanationwithinthe confines of a naturalistic scientificoutlook. Both sides of the debate have philosophy has been milling over the same issues and theories for developed theories about the nature of phenomenal consciousness two-and-a-half millennia.

We shall certainly devote attention to withspecificconsequencesfor scientificresearch. Weshallalsopay attention, however,to current sci- Another more specific problem about the mind is the puzzle of entific claims about freedom of the will. These claims have stirred intentionality and mental content.

This problem is not-oniy about a lot of debate in and outside of science. Do we ical one, for close analysis will reveal that they are not about the simulate the behaviour of others and project our own behavioural exact same issues. In Chapter 5 we will discuss and separate these tendencies onto others? Or is the mind less hidden behind behav- debates and explain why it is not the case that neuroscience is cur- iour than these two approaches assume?

What is the role of the rently deciding the philosophical issue of free will. Perhaps we can see much of what goes Chapter 6 will focus on the self. A hostofdifferent meanings on in the other's mind in facial expressions, gestures and bodily are connected with that term, ranging from a simple 'subject of postures? Arguably, the debate on these topics is one ofthe best ex- experience', to our most fundamental identities as persons.

But amples of collaboration between philosophy and behavioural and do selves exist? If so, how? If not, are they illusions? And what is brain science. Philosophical arguments are directly translated into the connection between our selves and consciousness?

Or between experimental set-ups such as the well-known 'false-belief task' , our selves and our bodies? And how can selves continue to exist and scientific findings, such asthe discovery of mirror neurons, are through time, given that most of us change considerably, both in quickly incorporated in philosophical theorizing. The main uncertainty that faced Descartes and his contemporaries, however, was not where interaction took place, but how two things so different as thought and extension could interact at all.

This would be particularly mysterious if one had an impact view of causal interaction, as would anyone influenced by atomism, for whom the paradigm of causation is like two billiard balls cannoning off one another. Various of Descartes' disciples, such as Arnold Geulincx and Nicholas Malebranche, concluded that all mind-body interactions required the direct intervention of God.

The appropriate states of mind and body were only the occasions for such intervention, not real causes. Now it would be convenient to think that occasionalists held that all causation was natural except for that between mind and body. In fact they generalized their conclusion and treated all causation as directly dependent on God. Why this was so, we cannot discuss here. Descartes' conception of a dualism of substances came under attack from the more radical empiricists, who found it difficult to attach sense to the concept of substance at all.

Locke, as a moderate empiricist, accepted that there were both material and immaterial substances. Berkeley famously rejected material substance, because he rejected all existence outside the mind. Finally, he decided that the self, conceived as something over and above the ideas of which it was aware, was essential for an adequate understanding of the human person.

Although the self and its acts are not presented to consciousness as objects of awareness, we are obliquely aware of them simply by dint of being active subjects.

Hume rejected such claims, and proclaimed the self to be nothing more than a concatenation of its ephemeral contents. In fact, Hume criticised the whole conception of substance for lacking in empirical content: when you search for the owner of the properties that make up a substance, you find nothing but further properties.

This position has been labelled bundle dualism, and it is a special case of a general bundle theory of substance, according to which objects in general are just organised collections of properties. The problem for the Humean is to explain what binds the elements in the bundle together. This is an issue for any kind of substance, but for material bodies the solution seems fairly straightforward: the unity of a physical bundle is constituted by some form of causal interaction between the elements in the bundle.

For the mind, mere causal connection is not enough; some further relation of co-consciousness is required. We shall see in 5.

[RIASSUNTO] MANDIK, Pete - This is Philosophy of Mind.pdf, Sintesi di Filosofia della Mente

One should note the following about Hume's theory. His bundle theory is a theory about the nature of the unity of the mind.

As a theory about this unity, it is not necessarily dualist. Parfit , and Shoemaker , ch. In general, physicalists will accept it unless they wish to ascribe the unity to the brain or the organism as a whole. Before the bundle theory can be dualist one must accept property dualism, for more about which, see the next section. A crisis in the history of dualism came, however, with the growing popularity of mechanism in science in the nineteenth century.

This means that everything that happens follows from and is in accord with the laws of physics. There is, therefore, no scope for interference in the physical world by the mind in the way that interactionism seems to require. According to the mechanist, the conscious mind is an epiphenomenon a notion given general currency by T.

Huxley : that is, it is a by-product of the physical system which has no influence back on it. In this way, the facts of consciousness are acknowledged but the integrity of physical science is preserved.

However, many philosophers found it implausible to claim such things as the following; the pain that I have when you hit me, the visual sensations I have when I see the ferocious lion bearing down on me or the conscious sense of understanding I have when I hear your argument—all have nothing directly to do with the way I respond.

It is very largely due to the need to avoid this counterintuitiveness that we owe the concern of twentieth century philosophy to devise a plausible form of materialist monism. But, although dualism has been out of fashion in psychology since the advent of behaviourism Watson and in philosophy since Ryle , the argument is by no means over.

Some distinguished neurologists, such as Sherrington and Eccles Popper and Eccles have continued to defend dualism as the only theory that can preserve the data of consciousness.

Amongst mainstream philosophers, discontent with physicalism led to a modest revival of property dualism in the last decade of the twentieth century. At least some of the reasons for this should become clear below. Varieties of Dualism: Ontology There are various ways of dividing up kinds of dualism. One natural way is in terms of what sorts of things one chooses to be dualistic about. The most common categories lighted upon for these purposes are substance and property, giving one substance dualism and property dualism.

There is, however, an important third category, namely predicate dualism.

Current Issues in the Philosophy of Mind

As this last is the weakest theory, in the sense that it claims least, I shall begin by characterizing it. For a mental predicate to be reducible, there would be bridging laws connecting types of psychological states to types of physical ones in such a way that the use of the mental predicate carried no information that could not be expressed without it.

An example of what we believe to be a true type reduction outside psychology is the case of water, where water is always H2O: something is water if and only if it is H2O.

But the terms in many of the special sciences that is, any science except physics itself are not reducible in this way. Not every hurricane or every infectious disease, let alone every devaluation of the currency or every coup d'etat has the same constitutive structure. These states are defined more by what they do than by their composition or structure. Their names are classified as functional terms rather than natural kind terms.

It goes with this that such kinds of state are multiply realizable; that is, they may be constituted by different kinds of physical structures under different circumstances. Because of this, unlike in the case of water and H2O, one could not replace these terms by some more basic physical description and still convey the same information.

It is widely agreed that many, if not all, psychological states are similarly irreducible, and so psychological predicates are not reducible to physical descriptions and one has predicate dualism. The classic source for irreducibility in the special sciences in general is Fodor , and for irreducibility in the philosophy of mind, Davidson Property dualism can be seen as a step stronger than predicate dualism.

One might say that we need more than the language of physics to describe and explain the weather, but we do not need more than its ontology. There is token identity between each individual hurricane and a mass of atoms, even if there is no type identity between hurricanes as kinds and some particular structure of atoms as a kind.

Genuine property dualism occurs when, even at the individual level, the ontology of physics is not sufficient to constitute what is there. The irreducible language is not just another way of describing what there is, it requires that there be something more there than was allowed for in the initial ontology. In the case of mind, property dualism is defended by those who argue that the qualitative nature of consciousness is not merely another way of categorizing states of the brain or of behaviour, but a genuinely emergent phenomenon.

One is that of substance, the other is the dualism of these substances. A substance is characterized by its properties, but, according to those who believe in substances, it is more than the collection of the properties it possesses, it is the thing which possesses them. So the mind is not just a collection of thoughts, but is that which thinks, an immaterial substance over and above its immaterial states. Properties are the properties of objects. If one is a property dualist, one may wonder what kinds of objects possess the irreducible or immaterial properties in which one believes.

One can use a neutral expression and attribute them to persons, but, until one has an account of person, this is not explanatory. One might attribute them to human beings qua animals, or to the brains of these animals. Then one will be holding that these immaterial properties are possessed by what is otherwise a purely material thing. But one may also think that not only mental states are immaterial, but that the subject that possesses them must also be immaterial.

Then one will be a dualist about that to which mental states and properties belong as well about the properties themselves. Now one might try to think of these subjects as just bundles of the immaterial states. This is Hume's view.

But if one thinks that the owner of these states is something quite over and above the states themselves, and is immaterial, as they are, one will be a substance dualist. Lowe, for example, is a substance dualist, in the following sense. He holds that a normal human being involves two substances, one a body and the other a person. The latter is not, however, a purely mental substance that can be defined in terms of thought or consciousness alone, as Descartes claimed.

But persons and their bodies have different identity conditions and are both substances, so there are two substances essentially involved in a human being, hence this is a form of substance dualism. Lowe claims that his theory is close to P. Strawson's , whilst admitting that Strawson would not have called it substance dualism. Varieties of Dualism: Interaction If mind and body are different realms, in the way required by either property or substance dualism, then there arises the question of how they are related.

Common sense tells us that they interact: thoughts and feelings are at least sometimes caused by bodily events and at least sometimes themselves give rise to bodily responses. I shall now consider briefly the problems for interactionism, and its main rivals, epiphenomenalism and parallelism. That this is so is one of our common-sense beliefs, because it appears to be a feature of everyday experience.

The physical world influences my experience through my senses, and I often react behaviourally to those experiences. My thinking, too, influences my speech and my actions. There is, therefore, a massive natural prejudice in favour of interactionism. It has been claimed, however, that it faces serious problems some of which were anticipated in section 1.

The simplest objection to interaction is that, in so far as mental properties, states or substances are of radically different kinds from each other, they lack that communality necessary for interaction. But if causation is either by a more ethereal force or energy or only a matter of constant conjunction, there would appear to be no problem in principle with the idea of interaction of mind and body.

Even if there is no objection in principle, there appears to be a conflict between interactionism and some basic principles of physical science.

For example, if causal power was flowing in and out of the physical system, energy would not be conserved, and the conservation of energy is a fundamental scientific law. Various responses have been made to this. One suggestion is that it might be possible for mind to influence the distribution of energy, without altering its quantity. See Averill and Keating Another response is to challenge the relevance of the conservation principle in this context.

Robins Collins has claimed that the appeal to conservation by opponents of interactionism is something of a red herring because conservation principles are not ubiquitous in physics. He argues that energy is not conserved in general relativity, in quantum theory, or in the universe taken as a whole. Why then, should we insist on it in mind-brain interaction?

This is a very natural assumption, but it is not justified if causal overdetermination of behaviour is possible. There could then be a complete physical cause of behaviour, and a mental one. The strongest intuitive objection against overdetermination is clearly stated by Mills , who is himself a defender of overdetermination.

For X to be a cause of Y, X must contribute something to Y. The only way a purely mental event could contribute to a purely physical one would be to contribute some feature not already determined by a purely physical event. But if physical closure is true, there is no feature of the purely physical effect that is not contributed by the purely physical cause. Hence interactionism violates physical closure after all. Mills says that this argument is invalid, because a physical event can have features not explained by the event which is its sufficient cause.

It is this kind of feature that the mental event would have to cause, but physical closure leaves no room for this. These matters are still controversial. The problem with closure of physics may be radically altered if physical laws are indeterministic, as quantum theory seems to assert. If physical laws are deterministic, then any interference from outside would lead to a breach of those laws.

The Philosophy of Mind-Wandering

But if they are indeterministic, might not interference produce a result that has a probability greater than zero, and so be consistent with the laws? This way, one might have interaction yet preserve a kind of nomological closure, in the sense that no laws are infringed.

Because it involves assessing the significance and consequences of quantum theory, this is a difficult matter for the non-physicist to assess. Some argue that indeterminacy manifests itself only on the subatomic level, being cancelled out by the time one reaches even very tiny macroscopic objects: and human behaviour is a macroscopic phenomenon. For discussion of this, see Eccles , , and Popper and Eccles Still others argue that quantum indeterminacy manifests itself directly at a high level, when acts of observation collapse the wave function, suggesting that the mind may play a direct role in affecting the state of the world Hodgson ; Stapp According to this theory, mental events are caused by physical events, but have no causal influence on the physical.

I have introduced this theory as if its point were to avoid the problem of how two different categories of thing might interact. In fact, it is, at best, an incomplete solution to this problem. If it is mysterious how the non-physical can have it in its nature to influence the physical, it ought to be equally mysterious how the physical can have it in its nature to produce something non-physical. But that this latter is what occurs is an essential claim of epiphenomenalism. For development of this point, see Green , — There are at least three serious problems for epiphenomenalism.

First, as I indicated in section 1, it is profoundly counterintuitive. What could be more apparent than that it is the pain that I feel that makes me cry, or the visual experience of the boulder rolling towards me that makes me run away?

At least one can say that epiphenomenalism is a fall-back position: it tends to be adopted because other options are held to be unacceptable. The second problem is that, if mental states do nothing, there is no reason why they should have evolved. This objection ties in with the first: the intuition there was that conscious states clearly modify our behaviour in certain ways, such as avoiding danger, and it is plain that they are very useful from an evolutionary perspective.

Frank Jackson replies to this objection by saying that it is the brain state associated with pain that evolves for this reason: the sensation is a by-product. Evolution is full of useless or even harmful by-products. For example, polar bears have evolved thick coats to keep them warm, even though this has the damaging side effect that they are heavy to carry. Jackson's point is true in general, but does not seem to apply very happily to the case of mind. The heaviness of the polar bear's coat follows directly from those properties and laws which make it warm: one could not, in any simple way, have one without the other.

But with mental states, dualistically conceived, the situation is quite the opposite. The laws of physical nature which, the mechanist says, make brain states cause behaviour, in no way explain why brain states should give rise to conscious ones. The laws linking mind and brain are what Feigl calls nomological danglers, that is, brute facts added onto the body of integrated physical law.

Why there should have been by-products of that kind seems to have no evolutionary explanation. The third problem concerns the rationality of belief in epiphenomenalism, via its effect on the problem of other minds. It is natural to say that I know that I have mental states because I experience them directly. But how can I justify my belief that others have them? I know that certain of my mental states are correlated with certain pieces of behaviour, and so I infer that similar behaviour in others is also accompanied by similar mental states.

Many hold that this is a weak argument because it is induction from one instance, namely, my own. I seem to know from my own case that mental events can be the explanation of behaviour, and I know of no other candidate explanation for typical human behaviour, so I postulate the same explanation for the behaviour of others. But if epiphenomenalism is true, my mental states do not explain my behaviour and there is a physical explanation for the behaviour of others.

It is explanatorily redundant to postulate such states for others. I know, by introspection, that I have them, but is it not just as likely that I alone am subject to this quirk of nature, rather than that everyone is?

For more detailed treatment and further reading on this topic, see the entry epiphenomenalism. The parallelist preserves both realms intact, but denies all causal interaction between them. They run in harmony with each other, but not because their mutual influence keeps each other in line. That they should behave as if they were interacting would seem to be a bizarre coincidence. This is why parallelism has tended to be adopted only by those—like Leibniz—who believe in a pre-established harmony, set in place by God.

The progression of thought can be seen as follows. Descartes believes in a more or less natural form of interaction between immaterial mind and material body. Malebranche thought that this was impossible naturally, and so required God to intervene specifically on each occasion on which interaction was required.

Leibniz decided that God might as well set things up so that they always behaved as if they were interacting, without particular intervention being required. Outside such a theistic framework, the theory is incredible. Even within such a framework, one might well sympathise with Berkeley's instinct that once genuine interaction is ruled out one is best advised to allow that God creates the physical world directly, within the mental realm itself, as a construct out of experience. Because this argument has its own entry see the entry qualia: the knowledge argument , I shall deal relatively briefly with it here.

One should bear in mind, however, that all arguments against physicalism are also arguments for the irreducible and hence immaterial nature of the mind and, given the existence of the material world, are thus arguments for dualism.

The knowledge argument asks us to imagine a future scientist who has lacked a certain sensory modality from birth, but who has acquired a perfect scientific understanding of how this modality operates in others. This scientist—call him Harpo—may have been born stone deaf, but become the world's greatest expert on the machinery of hearing: he knows everything that there is to know within the range of the physical and behavioural sciences about hearing.

Suppose that Harpo, thanks to developments in neurosurgery, has an operation which finally enables him to hear.

It is suggested that he will then learn something he did not know before, which can be expressed as what it is like to hear, or the qualitative or phenomenal nature of sound. These qualitative features of experience are generally referred to as qualia. If Harpo learns something new, he did not know everything before. He knew all the physical facts before.

So what he learns on coming to hear—the facts about the nature of experience or the nature of qualia—are non-physical. This establishes at least a state or property dualism.

See Jackson ; Robinson There are at least two lines of response to this popular but controversial argument. This essentially behaviouristic account is exactly what the intuition behind the argument is meant to overthrow. Putting ourselves in Harpo's position, it is meant to be obvious that what he acquires is knowledge of what something is like, not just how to do something. Such appeals to intuition are always, of course, open to denial by those who claim not to share the intuition.

Some ability theorists seem to blur the distinction between knowing what something is like and knowing how to do something, by saying that the ability Harpo acquires is to imagine or remember the nature of sound. In this case, what he acquires the ability to do involves the representation to himself of what the thing is like. But this conception of representing to oneself, especially in the form of imagination, seems sufficiently close to producing in oneself something very like a sensory experience that it only defers the problem: until one has a physicalist gloss on what constitutes such representations as those involved in conscious memory and imagination, no progress has been made.

The other line of response is to argue that, although Harpo's new knowledge is factual, it is not knowledge of a new fact. Rather, it is new way of grasping something that he already knew. Demonstrative concepts pick something out without saying anything extra about it.

Skip to main content. Log In Sign Up. Philosophy of mind, brain and behaviour. Marc Slors. Leon de Bruin. Derek Strijbos.

The Mind-Body Problem i7 i. Voor zover het maken van kopieen uk deze uitgave is toegestaan op grand van 1. Besluit van 2,7 november 2. Voor z. Consciousness 6i het overnemenvan gedeelte n uit dezeuitgave in bloemlezingen,readersen z.

Bas Smidt Verzorgingbinnenwerk: StevenBoland Afbeelding omslag: Intentionality ISBN 3. Internalism, externalism, and beyond Ill www. Mental Causation 9. Emotion z85 4. The problem of explanatoryexclusion 9. The science of conscious control 5.

Quantum Physics Meets the Philosophy of Mind

EmbodiedEmbeddedCognition zzy 7. Radicallyembodiedembeddedcognition 7. Social Cognition 8.

What is subjectivity, for that matter? Does it require a 'self, or a subject of experience? If so, whatisthat? Isthatevena possibilitywhenall we think and do emerges from the physical brain? These are pro- totypical questions that characterize the philosophy ofmind, brain and behaviour that we shall introduce in this book. Many of the problems and theories we shall discuss fall under what is known as analytical philosophy of mind. There are prob- ably few academic disciplines that can boast of as many truly ex- cellent textbooks as analytical philosophy of mind.

So why write another one? The reason is that we will include a considerably wid- er array of topics and methods than is usual in the discipline of philosophy of mind - hence the label 'philosophy of mind, brain and behaviour.

There are a number of themes that are closely related to these but which fall just outside of the boundaries of the philosophy of mind, narrowly conceived. These themes usually do not make it into the textbooks. What they have in common with questions about the nature of mind, mental content, mental causation and conscious- ness, however, is that they are directly connected with the bigger issue of whatit is that makes us human beings.

Or better: They will tion or a set of defining characteristics is as difficult as providing a be included in this book. Analytical philosophy, with its focus of And yet: In the past decades precise conceptual analysis, does play a major role.

But we shall muchprogress hasbeenmade in analysing concepts such asthink- also pay attention to the phenomenological tradition in philoso- ing, consciousness or freedom of the will. This doesn't mean that phy, which emphasizes the importance of the analysis of experience we now have simple definitions that can function as uncontrover- itself. Furthermore, we will pay explicit attention to the relation sial explications for science butit doesmeanthatwehavesophisti- between the philosophy of mind, brain and behaviour, and the catedtheoriesthat are non-circularandinformative.

Most ofthese science thereof. The term explainingthemind andits features in line withthenatural scienc- 'mind' is used here as an umbrella term. It refers to all states, capac- es. Some arguments are intended to show that specific attempts at ities and processes that we would normally call 'mental':And how can selves continue to exist and scientific findings, such asthe discovery of mirror neurons, are through time, given that most of us change considerably, both in quickly incorporated in philosophical theorizing.

What is the role of the rently deciding the philosophical issue of free will. You cannot combine just any matter with any form—you cannot make a knife out of butter, nor a human being out of paper—so the nature of the matter is a necessary condition for the nature of the substance. These topics are 'the self, 'free will', 'understanding other minds', 'embodied, embedded cognition' and 'emotions'.

Hume seems, however, in the main text to unconsciously make a concession to the opposing view, namely the view that there must be something more than the items in the bundle to make up a mind. Click here to sign up. This affinity is so strong that the soul strives to leave the body in which it is imprisoned and to dwell in the realm of Forms. His bundle theory is a theory about the nature of the unity of the mind.

AUDREA from Waterbury
I relish sharing PDF docs punctually. Look over my other articles. One of my extra-curricular activities is dancing.
>